koganbot: (Default)
Frank Kogan ([personal profile] koganbot) wrote2010-07-03 07:51 am

Richard Rorty 2: Propositions and stuff

For a person to form a predicative judgment is for him to come to believe a sentence to be true. For a Kantian transcendental ego to come to believe a sentence to be true is for it to relate representations (Vorstellungen) to one another: two radically distinct sorts of representations, concepts on the one hand and intuitions on the other. Kant provided a framework for understanding the confusing seventeenth-century intellectual scene when he said that "Leibniz intellectualized appearances, just as Locke... sensualized all concepts of the understanding." He thereby created the standard version of "the history of modern philosophy" according to which pre-Kantian philosophy was a struggle between "rationalism," which wanted to reduce sensations to concepts, and "empiricism," which wanted the inverse reduction. Had Kant instead said that the rationalists wanted to find a way of replacing propositions about secondary qualities with propositions which somehow did the same job but were known with certainty, and that the empiricists opposed this project, the next two centuries of philosophical thought might have been very different. For if the "problem of knowledge" had been stated in terms of the relations between propositions and the degree of certainty attaching to them, rather than the terms of putative components of propositions, we might not have inherited our present notion of "the history of philosophy." According to standard neo-Kantian historiography, from the time of the Phaedo and Metaphysics Z through Abelard and Anselm, Locke and Leibniz, and right down to Quine and Strawson reflection which was distinctively philosophical has concerned the relation between universals and particulars. Without this unifying theme, we might not have been able to see a continuous problematic, discovered by the Greeks and worried at continuously down to our own day, and thus might never have had the notion of "philosophy" as something with a twenty-five-hundred-year history. Greek thought and seventeenth-century thought might have seemed as distinct both from each other and from our present concerns as, say, Hindu theology and Mayan numerology.
--Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, 1979, pp 148-149.

I'm rereading chapters 3 and 4 of Richard Rorty's Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature with the intention of trying to master them. My difficulty isn't the complexity of the ideas, since he's trying to be clear and not overcomplex, but that he assumes familiarity with various writers not all of whom I've read much of, and he'll use terms of art that I'm not all that familiar with; he also can be fast with his reasons (coming a sentence or two short, so you have to fill them in yourself) and vague and glib in presenting his own ideas, though the ideas are rarely glib themselves. So he often doesn't do right by his own complexities, doesn't come up with the detail and precision that he needs, doesn't have the fierce search for the best word that a Wittgenstein has, will futz along with tired old vocabulary that doesn't do the job. That said, he's got a broad historical and cultural view that Wittgenstein doesn't even try for. He gets Wittgenstein's challenge to philosophy - the import of Wittgenstein's complaint that language goes on holiday in philosophy is that philosophy isn't addressing the questions its vocabulary cons itself into thinking it's addressing - but Rorty goes on to ask why intelligent people thought (and maybe still think) the issues mattered, asks what assumptions they were making, what they thought was at stake. For better or worse I've not only bought into Rorty's narrative of modern philosophy - which at least to undereducated me clarifies and puts into perspective a whole lot of material - but I've also copped the questions he asks: what's at stake, what do people think is at stake, what do I think is at stake, what assumptions are they making, what assumptions am I making, what else might be at issue if we stepped aside from this issue, and so forth.

About the passage I quoted: it comes in the middle of chapter 3; I'm going to circle back, but I liked this quote for its long view, its implied questions (what's going on in Plato and Descartes and Locke that Kant didn't teach us to look for, and that gets obscured if seen through Kantian eyes? what's going on with us that our Kantian heritage gets in the way of our seeing?). Some semi-random thoughts:

(1) "...the rationalists wanted to find a way of replacing propositions about secondary qualities with propositions which somehow did the same job but were known with certainty, and... the empiricists opposed this project." Rorty clearly thinks that this is a better way than Kant's of describing what the "rationalists" and the "empiricists" were up to. But he's not claiming that this is how the "rationalists" and "empiricists" would have described it themselves.

(2) "Predicative" may be a key word - the subsection is entitled "Kant's Confusion of Predication with Synthesis" - but I don't immediately see its import, actually. In a sentence, a predicate gives us an attribute of a subject (e.g., "You are sad") or tells us something a subject does ("You ran to the store crying") or something that is done to a subject ("You were mistreated, by me"). A "predicative judgment" means a judgment put in sentence form, but so what? What's so interesting about sentence form?

(3) I think that Rorty considers Kant to be making a mistake in relating the components of a sentence, rather than affirming or disconfirming the sentence as a whole. But I'm also certain that Rorty would follow Quine and Kuhn and Wittgenstein in taking sentences not to stand alone but to only be true (or make sense) in the context of a whole lot of other stuff, so again, what's the big deal about a sentence? Or conversely, what's a problem with a component?

(4) Throughout the chapter, the words "sentence" and, especially, "proposition" function as buzzwords. They're continually brought up; also brought up is that there are "relations" to and between propositions; but I have no idea why Rorty thinks sentences and propositions are more relevant here than are notions, ideas, formulas, theories, paragraphs, chapters, rants, spiels, arguments, contentions, social practices, language games, conventions, behaviors, events, and so forth. In fact, given that Rorty endorses Quine's holism (Quine said that statements can be neither confirmed nor disconfirmed in isolation from their fellows), I'm not getting why Rorty thinks that propositions and sentences, and subjects and predicates, are particularly at issue, as opposed to the overall behavior of sociolinguistic creatures, i.e., human beings. And the "relations" at issue would be social relations, I'd think, not merely relations among propositions. "Proposition" seems just as reductive as "sense impression" and the Kantian "concept" and "intuition." In any event, while Locke's and Kant's ideas get carefully examined in this chapter, phrases like "relations between propositions" just kind of show up, without explication or elaboration. To understand, I may have to translate into different or better terminology. Obviously Rorty chose "sentences" and "propositions" for reasons that matter to him and it would be good if I could work out what those are; and he's read scads on the subject of "propositions" that I haven't by Moore, Carnap, Ayer et al. Presumably Locke and Kant talked about "propositions," though I don't know what they said on the subject. But honestly I don't get why Rorty is using those words here, since his basic point as far as I can tell doesn't have to do with "sentences"/"propositions" in particular. Rather, it's that inquiry and justification are fundamentally social and conversational. "Stuff people say and write that they can argue about" would be more accurate, would better reflect what Rorty is trying to say; whereas "sentence," "proposition," and "predicate" sound linguistically precise and all, but in fact I don't think he's being technical or precise with them. EDIT: Oh yeah, as Mark and I talk about in the comments, when Kant defines "analytic" and "synthetic" it's in relation to subject and predicates, which implies sentence form. But since Rorty is talking about concepts and intuitions, I still don't get why sentences/propositions are particularly at issue or, even if they were a bit at issue for Kant, why Rorty should go along with this.

(5) The phrase "relations between propositions and the degree of certainty attaching to them" is ambiguous. It could mean relations between (a) propositions and (b) other propositions, some being more certain than others, which is what I'm pretty sure Rorty means (given what he'd said earlier in the paragraph about propositions concerning secondary qualities versus those somehow known with more certainty). But it could mean relations between (a) propositions and (b) degrees of certainty, though "degrees of certainty" would seem to be a judgment, not something you relate to. Earlier in the chapter he'd used the phrase "relations between persons and propositions," which I'd also found baffling.

(6) "Representations" is a key word too, though Rorty believes the confusion here is Locke's and Kant's, and Rorty is trying to disentangle it. A representative is an emissary, but of what?

(7) "For if the 'problem of knowledge' had been stated in terms of the relations between propositions and the degree of certainty attaching to them, rather than the terms of putative components of propositions, we might not have inherited our present notion of 'the history of philosophy.'" Not quite getting this, either. For Kant, the relation between "intuitions" (a.k.a. "sense impressions," right?) and "concepts" is that the intuitions are never known directly but only as "synthesized" by concepts - intuitions being many, hence in need of synthesis. (I don't remember my Kant: are the concepts embodied by the intuitions? If you never get the intuitions directly, how do you know if the concepts are embodied, or that they even exist? Did Kant feel he'd laid Hume's skepticism to rest?) Are intuitions components of propositions? How could they be? I'd think that only concepts could be, and I'm not even sure of that. Can't there be a concept that needs to be expressed in more than one proposition? How is a concept a component of a proposition? Words and clauses and the like are components, but concepts? Kant thinks he's describing the components of experience, right? Well, someone who's read more of Kant than I have needs to help me here. A sentence "synthesizes" a subject and an attribute, but neither the subject nor the attribute are intuitions. They've been pre-synthesized, as it were. Right? [EDIT: Well, I'm confused by the word "synthesis" here. Such defects arise when I haven't read the relevant Kant material for 34 years. Would Kant reserve "synthesis" for what a predicate does for a "synthetic" statement's subject (it adds info not already part of the subject's concept), or does he also use it for what concepts do for intuitions, which Rorty's text leads me to believe? Or are they somehow the same thing? See my inconsistent comments about this in the comment thread.]

(8) Whenever Rorty says "If we think in terms of A rather than B, we will ______," I see red flags and hear warning sirens. Such statements always oversimplify his own ideas, and in making them he's casually asserting what he I think he intends to be challenging, that philosophical suppositions are fundamental to life ("philosophical" pertaining to "philosophy" as its definition and history was narrowed owing to Kant).

(9) Why don't we just say, "The rationalists wanted to derive secondary qualities of stuff from stuff that was known with certainty, and the empiricists opposed this project"? And we can say, "If the 'problem of knowledge' had been stated in terms of how to give good reasons for the stuff you believe and the degree of certainty attaching to your reasons, rather than in terms of how our mind supposedly constitutes stuff, we might not have inherited our present notion of 'the history of philosophy'"? I absolutely don't see any value in adding the word "proposition" to the thought, or what we lose by its absence - whereas its presence creates confusion, by adding the very unclear (to me, anyway) idea that "intuitions" and "concepts" (as Kant uses those terms) are components of propositions, as well as the mystifying talk of relations to or between propositions. I suppose its presence would correctly allude to the fact that when we give reasons we tend to do so through speech or writing, which often includes sentences. But so what? And why sentences as opposed to longer utterances?

(10) Despite what one might infer from the final sentence of the quoted passage, Rorty doesn't think that Greek philosophy and 17th century philosophy are unrelated. In the previous subsection he presents Locke as having one foot in Aristotle and one foot not, and in the next he talks of the ocular metaphor that Locke and Kant carry forward from Plato. What Rorty is attacking is the idea that you can discover within all of Western philosophy (and Western life) a distinction between what is given to us in experience and what is added by the mind - the distinction can also be thought of as a distinction between particulars and universals - and a concern with such a distinction. (The meaning of "philosophy" is also at issue here, since, if no one can find that distinction in your thought, post-Kant you might not get called a philosopher, or so Rorty claims. [I'm pretty sure he's speaking of what you might get called in philosophy departments, as opposed to, say, in politics, or used bookstores.])

(11) Even though I've been picking at it, I like the quoted passage very much.

(12) I'm calling this post "Richard Rorty 2"; I've ex post facto gone and called this one "1." For other Rorty-relevant stuff (esp. this one) click the Rorty tab.

[identity profile] dubdobdee.livejournal.com 2010-07-04 09:30 am (UTC)(link)
The actual word "proposition" doesn't appear as such in the index to the Critique of Pure Reason. I wouldn't be astonished if a word Kant used had been translated as "proposition"; but I also wouldn't be astonished if translator Norman Kemp Smith, working in the 1920s, the zenith of Bertrand Russell's era, deliberately avoided it (as somewhat anachronistic and misleading). It doesn't get grabbed as an official concept-tool until the emergence of modern propositional logic, and algebras of logic, with George Boole, Charles Peirce and others.

This isn't to say that Aristotelian logic doesn't have similarities -- logic being explained via examples and model sentences in propositional form ("therefore socrates is a man" etc) (haha in greek these examplar setennces would be called PARADIGMS) but I suspect that the actual algebraicisation is important to the momentum of the tendency Rorty is criticising.

I would also (intuitively)* suggest that Kant and Hegel would have been suspicious of algebraic logic not as a tool (they both had high regard for mathematics) but as a master-too. That it doesn't develop as a problem for the discussion of philsophy unti lthe emergence of departments of philosophy* defending the boundaries of their specific discipline which also require students to have mastered the relevant logical calculus as a basic technique (very likely before entirely understanding its uses and limits)

*ie from a general sense of the kinds of errors they attacked and understanding they were attempting to inculcate: i have no passages to cite, not least because the notion may never have occurred to either to discuss (will expand on this if needed)
**Philosophy as an academic discipline more or less invented by Kant and Hegel, in the sense that they were key to its having departmental offices in the modern university as it emerged in Germany in the late 18th century

[identity profile] dubdobdee.livejournal.com 2010-07-04 09:36 am (UTC)(link)
That's a long answer to a single -- possibly not central! -- sentence in 4.

I will try and gin up a crash course in Kant over the next few days! He did indeed believe he'd laid Hume's scepticism to rest.

(I imagine I explained* some Kantian stuff before -- I shall go back and have a look.)

*"explained"

[identity profile] dubdobdee.livejournal.com 2010-07-06 09:47 am (UTC)(link)
after a quick glance thru critique of pure reason before i went to bed last night, i concluded that
(a) the word "sentence" does not itself appear in the index
(b) the word "ego" appears in the index, immediately redirecting us to the word "self"
(c) the "transcedental self" is indeed distinct from the (normal?) self -- i couldn't find it explicitly defined (though by then i was feeling drowsy) but yes, i take it that it is the constitutive but to us hidden underlying operation which allows our aware self to exist and function as we know it does
(d) hence "to relate" in that extract is not a conscious deliberative act, but a preconscious necessity prior to any possible thought or act

kant doesn't talk about "believing sentences to be true" in so many words -- this i think is back-formation from the later reaches of this history -- but he does for example discuss analytic and synthetic judgments in terms of subjects and predicates (which kept together would always form sentences).

I still have to re-remember kant's particular distinction between concepts and intutions before i can master the last section of that quote, however -- bright morning and strong coffee not yet enough!
(my suspicion is that there's a terminological anachronism here which rorty would justify by noting that he is describing the continuous history of an error: since the neo-kantians argued X, and derived it from kant, then kant must also to all intents and purposes have believed X, albeit in different types of phrasing)

[identity profile] dubdobdee.livejournal.com 2010-07-08 09:22 am (UTC)(link)
FUCK! i just spent 40 minutes writing a reply to this, which was too long for the post and i pressed the wrong button and lost it all >:(

Things that are slightly wrong here, Kant-wise (i)

[identity profile] dubdobdee.livejournal.com 2010-07-08 12:41 pm (UTC)(link)
(Dredged from fallible memory and speed-reading on the bus -- then ett by computer and painfully reconstructed)

Concepts are a priori while intuitions are a posteriori
No, plenty of -- most? -- concepts are also a posteriori, in Kant's scheme of things. He is on the hunt for concepts that are a priori, because they are the key to his proof that inside and outside -- in the schemes conjured up by his proto-modern predecessors (from Descartes via Locke and Berkley to Hume and Leibniz), these seem to have been sundered from one another. He amplifies the division in order to bridge it more successfully and completely -- at least, that's the intention of his project, though this rhetorical amplification ends up with a far greater role in subsequent "philosophy as it should be practiced" than it ought to, if he had indeed successfully built the bridge. (Because what was adopted was the technique?)
The concepts Kant concludes are a priori are cap-T Time and cap-S Space -- my caps, to be clearer shortly. Small t-time and small-s space are of course given us via intuitions: cf such sentences as "Look, there's still space in this cupboard" and "The train is on time". Kant's argument is that Space and Time the a priori concepts do NOT simply emerge as conceptualised aggregates of all the spca-and-time intuitions we're given., Because we need them in advance, as conditions of possibility of consciousness at all. Without a pre-constituted armature of structure through which our experiences, intuitions, perceptions and a posteriori concepts all pass, consciousness as we experience simply couldn't happen.
He goes further. Cap-t Time and Cap-s Space are not given to us, as such. They're NOT inherent Iin the great out there. They're what we bring to the experience picnic, to structure our experiences. The hard-wired bridging mechanism, if you like, between living thought and not-necessarily living matter. These seems very peculiar -- and I believe (as he did) entirely original to Kant. The corollary of this is his science-fictional nightmare: the noumenal vs the phenomenal. Which again seems hugely to stress a separation, the very separation he is urgently striving to overcome.
It's a little unjust to say he just asserts, re the nature of the noumenon. (I'm tempted to argue he confuses matters by discussing noumena plural, since plurlity is surely a phenomenal quality...) Basically he defines it -- as that which we can perhaps understand (in the abstract) to exist, and the forms it must take, but can't imagine viewing or really grasp. I think the noumenon seems less peculiar if we get down to cases (but what follows is me trying to firm up his idea, not him).
Right, so we are hairless mammals in a hostile world. We are yea-high and to orientate ourselves and judge what is to hand that's dangerous or good for us, we use an evolved perceptual machinery which is highly selective. We can see an object's front as it presents to us, for example -- but not the entirely of its insides, or (without optical aids) whatever parts are facing away from us. We encounter a moving or changing object as a succession of intuitions -- we do not and cannot see its whole, from beginning to end, in one go, complete with all in-between stages. Both these ideas are comprehensible -- the idea of them is imaginable -- but the machineries of our perception prevent us (or have not evoled to allow us?) from "seeing" in this manner. (Mathematics -- geometry especially -- allows us other ways to explore such notions, of course.)

correction a

[identity profile] dubdobdee.livejournal.com 2010-07-08 12:44 pm (UTC)(link)
they are the key to his proof that inside and outside
s/b
they are the key to his proof that inside and outside are inextricably and necessarily linked

Things that are slightly wrong here, Kant-wise (ii)

[identity profile] dubdobdee.livejournal.com 2010-07-08 12:42 pm (UTC)(link)
The all-in-one-go at-every-stage front-back-and-insides object is a noumenon, by Kant's definition. It is beyond us to perceive in this manner, yet -- in his argument -- this is how the world "out there" actually exists. For whatever reasons (Darwinian, perhaps: but of course Darwin came many decades later) our actual physical bodies and their workings decline to grasp the "whole" (the noumenon) in one go. We vastly prioritise the facing side of things nearby, right now. We -- as conscious entities -- pass across or through the noumenon in a particular, limited, filtered, finite way.
Berkeley -- for example -- argued that "outside" didn't exist at all (this Kant refers to as dogmatic idealism). Descartes proposed non-existence in order to focus on what he considered an infallible judgment (this Kant refers to as problematic idealism). Kant's argument is that the noumenon has to exist, and "outside" any given consciousness, because there has to be something that anchors and keeps distinct the "movie-images" to come together to give us the sense of time passing, which is a necessary ground for consciousness-as-we-experience-it. But ff cap-T Time inhered in the noumenon -- rather than arriving as a consequence of the machineries of our perceptual porocesses -- outside and inside would collapse together; Berkeley's idealism might as well be true, and consciousness as we know it -- including ourself the existing self -- would not be possible (oof: something like that, anyway...)
Kant and Kantian historiographers incorrectly project back onto earlier philosophy
This is true if a little unfair: in a book of 700 pages, Kant devotes three and a bit to a sketchy restatement of the entire history of philosophy, insofaras it pertains to his object of interest. So yes, he does somewhat recruit his predecessors to one or other side of the argument he is resolving. But he isn't claiming that everything they said boils down to this -- even if his professionalising successors decided that's what he meant. My assumption is that he hoped, with the Critique of Pure Reason, to DISPENSE once and for all with a particular annoying distraction of a conundrum, raised implicitly by Descartes and explicitly and provocatively by Hume. So that we could go back to eg Plato and Epicurus and Aristotle and etc, and strip out this small annoying section -- as a problem solved by Kant by Copernican means -- and concentrate on everything ELSE they discussed.

(ok i still haven't got to any of the actual puzzling questions you asked about, re sentences and etc)

mama's gonna takes us to the noo tomorrow

[identity profile] dubdobdee.livejournal.com 2010-07-08 04:25 pm (UTC)(link)
Ooh I forgot this little bit in my reconstruction of my original lost answer: Kant does use the word "empiricists"; however his word for members of the opposing camp is not "rationalists" but "noologists"

wild guesswork

[identity profile] dubdobdee.livejournal.com 2010-07-04 09:51 am (UTC)(link)
The abolition of social relations as a vital element in thought, understanding and reason probably arrives with Descartes, whose tool was to dispense with all fallible claims, which takes him inside his own head communing with a God who can maybe lie to him.

But actually i suspect the empiricists also downgrade the social dimension -- however I haven't reread Locke for 30 years (I always found him a big far bore); and Hume -- while chatty and clubbable in tone -- is cheerfully derisive about what people merely say and think. (Marxist phlilosophers would make a lot at this point of the centrality to Locke's and Hume's politics of the property-owning individual as the "atom of right" or some such)

Kant was focused on defanging Hume in Critique of Pure Reason; his later works -- about for example morality and aesthetics -- pay far more attention on the social world, albeit sometimes in a somewhat abstracted form; but reason (for Kant) puts the social world at bay.

Hegel explicitly brings it back in: the role of history in the development of reason is a reintroduction of the idea that understanding is always social -- and hence, since all so-far-exisiting societies are flawed, always flawed. (Marx of course brings the material relation of understanding with the social right to the forefront: there's a -- much-contested! -- reading of Marx which is surprsingly close to the pragmatists; certainly Marx himself regarded philosophy as a filibuster, a secular reaffirmation of churchly and reactionary values)